Wooden Iron? Husserlian Phenomenology Meets Cognitive Science

Tim van Gelder

University of Melbourne

Introduction

[1] Consciousness comes in many forms. One of these is so-called time consciousness. This is not consciousness of Time itself, nor is it simply consciousness that takes place in time. Rather, to put the point somewhat cryptically, it is consciousness of temporal objects as temporal. A temporal object is anything that exists in time, or endures. Rocks, chairs, conversations, tides, tunes, and empires all endure. In this respect they contrast with, for example, numbers. Time consciousness is a special kind of awareness of temporal objects - an awareness of them as enduring. It is the difference between my thinking abstractly of Nirvana's "Smells Like Teen Spirit," and my hearing it play on the radio. In the latter case, though not the former, the song actually unfolds in time and my awareness is an awareness of it as happening in time. The situation is essentially similar (though less dramatic) in the case of temporal objects such as chairs, which do not depend on change in time to be what they are.

[2] A moment's reflection can generate an interesting puzzle about time consciousness. Both the song and my awareness exist in time. They are like parallel tracks in the same time frame. However, as we standardly think about time, only the present and what is in it actually exist; thus, only a momentary stage of the song, and a momentary stage of my awareness, actually exist at any given time. The other stages did exist, or will exist, but do not exist now. It seems plausible, then, that my awareness at this moment of the music must be an awareness of the song now, i.e., of the current, momentary stage of the stage. The other stages do not exist, so how could I be aware of them? And here's the puzzle: if at any given time I am just aware of that part of the song that is playing now, how can I ever be aware of the song as an integrated piece that takes place over time?

[3] It is not being claimed that this puzzle is a deep metaphysical difficulty, like Zeno's paradoxes. Rather, it is a provocative way to point out an interesting theoretical domain. It is an entry point into serious reflection on the nature of time conciousness. How is time consciousness possible?

[4]  Presumably, an understanding of time consciousness should be part of an understanding of the nature of consciousness in general. Our philosophical and scientific tradition offers at least two major approaches to the study of mind and consciousness: phenomenology and cognitive science. These approaches are patently different in almost every important respect: they have their own literature, practitioners, professional meetings, vocabulary, methods, etc. They have fundamentally different orientations: phenomenology proceeds from the assumption that the study of mind must be rooted in direct attention to the nature of (one's own) experience, whereas cognitive science proceeds from the assumption that a genuine science of mind must be rooted in the observation of publicly available aspects of minds of others.

[5] To which of these approaches - phenomenology or cognitive science - should we turn for an understanding of time consciousness? They are sometimes regarded as direct competitors. Philosophical arguments have been adduced to demonstrate that genuine knowledge of consciousness can only be achieved by one method or the other. The position taken here, however, is that these conclusions are unwarranted; phenomenology and cognitive science should be regarded not only as compatible, but as mutually constraining and enriching approaches to the study of mind. This paper attempts a kind of "proof by example" of this position. It will demonstrate how both phenomenology and cognitive science can shed light on the phenomenon of time consciousness, and how their respective contributions can inform each other. The claim will be that only phenomenology and cognitive science in conjunction can adequately resolve the paradox of time consciousness described above.

Phenomenology and Time Consciousness

[6]  The most sustained investigation of time consciousness in the phenomenological tradition was that undertaken by Edmund Husserl. He visited the topic periodically throughout his life, and his written treatments of the topic are scattered throughout his work (notable collections of Husserl's writings on time consciousness are Husserl 1964, Husserl 1966). To make matters worse, Husserl's writings are notoriously difficult for the non-specialist reader. Fortunately, there are now a number of admirably clear and comprehensive presentations of Husserl's thought on time consciousness available in the secondary literature, including especially those by Brough, Miller, and Blattner (see Blattner ms., Brough 1989, Miller 1984). The reader is referred to those works for thorough treatments of the topic. In this section, I will relate, in highly simplified form, just enough of Husserl's account for the major purposes of this paper.(1)

[7] The upshot of the paradox of time consciousness is clear. When I am aware of something temporal as temporal, there is more to my awareness than simply a succession of momentary awarenesses of momentary stages. When I hear a melody, I don't simply hear this note now and another note a moment later. Something more is going on - but what could that be?

[8] An all-too-obvious move is to suggest that what we need, over and above the succession of momentary awarenesses, is an additional awareness of all the stages of the temporal object as comprising a single temporally extended entity. Husserl, attributing a view along these lines to Meinong, puts it this way: "there must be an act which embraces, beyond the now, the whole temporal object" (Husserl 1966: 226; quoted by Brough 1989: 266). Since this additional awareness cannot, by its very nature, take place until all the momentary stages have actually occurred, it must take place at the end of the succession of awarenesses.

[9] Husserl demonstrated that this view cannot be correct, however. For one thing, it is hard to see how this final all-embracing awareness can actually take place, for there is nothing left for it to embrace. By the time the final act takes place, the momentary stages of the object itself and the momentary awarenesses of those stages have been and gone; they are fully in the past, and in that sense no longer exist. One might attempt to remedy the situation by stipulating that one retains memories of the momentary stages of the object, and the final awareness combines those memories into an awareness of the entire temporal object. However, even as amended this way, the Meinongian suggestion falls afoul of another distinctively phenomenological objection. If you attend to your experience in being aware of a temporal object, you find yourself aware of that object as temporal even as time unfolds. When you listen to a melody, you don't have to wait around until the melody is finished in order to hear it as a melody.

[10] The key to solving the puzzle is to realize that, as Husserl put it, "consciousness must reach out beyond the now" (Husserl 1966: 227; quoted by Brough 1989: 267). Every momentary awareness of the temporal object must be an awareness of more than just the corresponding momentary stage of the temporal object. Consciousness must at that moment somehow relate the momentary stage of the temporal object to other stages, i.e., to what went before and what is to come. Husserl's theory of time consciousness is a sophisticated account of how awareness can build the past and the future into the present. It is thus a detailed theory of what is required for there to be any time consciousness (of the sort we have) at all.

[11] The basic insight is that every momentary stage or "act" of time consciousness actually has a triple structure (see figure 1). The centerpiece is a "primal impression" of the momentary stage of the temporal object. This primal impression corresponds roughly to the momentary awarenesses that figured in the Meinongian account. It simply takes in or "intends" what is now, in a way that is completely oblivious of what went before and what is to come. However, on Husserl's theory, primal impressions do not stand alone; they are only part of the triple structure that is essential to any individual act of time consciousness. Put differently, primal impressions are not awarenesses in their own right; they are essential ingredients or "moments" of full-blooded awarenesses of temporal objects.

Figure 1: Husserl's triple structure of time consciousness.

[12] The other ingredients of time consciousness are retentions and protentions. These are also intendings of stages of the temporal object. What distinguishes them from primal impressions, however, is that retentions are intendings of past stages, whereas protentions are intendings of future stages. For a crude illustration, imagine hearing the tune "Yankee Doodle," and consider your awareness of the tune at the time of the second note, i.e., corresponding to the "-kee." Roughly speaking, on Husserl's account, your perceptual time consciousness of the tune as a whole at that very moment has a triple structure of intendings: a primal impression of the second note ("-kee"), a retention of the first note ("Yan-"), and a protention of the third note ("Doo-").

[13] Husserl's theory of the triple structure of time consciousness clearly accounts, in broad outline, for how my awareness now can build in the past and the future, and thus be an awareness now of the temporal object as temporal. However, it does so at the cost of invoking what seem to be rather mysterious beasts, retentions and protentions. Why mysterious? Well, go back to the original paradox of time consciousness. What is past has disappeared forever, and what is future has not happened yet. In an obvious sense, both past and future don't exist now. The mystery is: how can retentions and protentions "intend" what doesn't exist? Or rather, what are retentions and protentions, such that it makes some kind of sense to say that they do this?

[14] Husserl explores the notions of retention and protention, and their role in time consciousness, in great depth and detail, but it is not clear that he succeeds in clarifying these notions enough to remove the sense of mystery. The suggestion made in this paper is that this mystery can only really be resolved once Husserl's theory is fleshed out by reference to actual models, from cognitive science, of the causal mechanisms underlying time consciousness. Before looking at those models, however, more of Husserl's account needs to be on the table. The following is a simplified and synthesized list of properties that Husserl ascribed to retention:

  1. Current.
    Retentions happen "now"; they are components of the current phase of consciousness, even though they are directed upon stages of the temporal object that are in the past.
  2. Intending of a stage as past to some degree.
    A retention must do more than be directed upon a stage of the temporal object that happens to be past (e.g., the first note of the tune). In order to have coherent awareness of a temporal object, the "pastness" of past stages must somehow figure in the picture; the temporal relations among the stages must be preserved in the way they are presented. Husserl makes this point by stipulating that retentions present past stages "as past to some degree." When I hear the third note of Yankee Doodle, my awareness of the tune includes retentions of both the first and the second notes, but the retention of the first note presents it as further in the past than the retention of the second.
  3. "Modifications" of primal impressions.
    A primal impression at one moment becomes a retention at the next. A primal impression is, by its very nature, directed upon the current momentary stage of the temporal object. As soon as that stage is past, the intending of it which is a necessary part of time consciousness has become a retention. This might be put by saying that retentions are impressions that are past their prime.
  4. Continuous manifold.
    In a given act of time consciousness, retentions, the primal impression, and protentions form a "continuous manifold." That is, there is an infinite number of retentions and protentions directed at vanishingly small past and future slices of the temporal object. In fact, it is probably misleading to talk of retentions and protentions at all, i.e., to use the terms "retention" and "protention" as count nouns. Rather, there are retentional and protentional regions of the whole intentional manifold which comprises the momentary act of time consciousness. It is preferable to use retention and protention as mass rather than count nouns.
  5. Finite.
    The manifold itself is not infinite in extent. That is, retention and protention are not directed arbitrarily far into the past and future. One retains and protends only stages of the temporal object within limited bounds of the current moment. When in the middle of a Mahler symphony (which can seem to go on forever), one's awareness of the music does not (typically) retain the opening notes or protend the final notes.
  6. Direct: not memories, images, or echoes.
    How can I be conscious now of something which is not now and hence, in a sense, does not actually exist? One possibility is that I am conscious of another thing which does exist now, and which has the function of (re)presenting that temporal stage. This kind of consciousness of the not-now is indirect; it travels via something that is now. Husserl, however, is adamant that this is not how retention intends past temporal stages. Retention is not a matter of having images of a past stage. Retention is not having memories which recreate the past as if it were now; nor is it like echoes still hanging around in the now. As Brough puts it: "Retention does not transmute what is absent into something present; it presents the absent in its absence" (276). Retention reaches out directly into the past. It is more like perceiving than representing.
  7. Perceptual.
    Except, one might object, that retention can't be perceptual in character. Why? Because the temporal stages upon which it is directed in an important sense no longer exist. The past has been and gone, and so cannot be literally perceived. Husserl was aware of this difficulty. Of retention, he says: "But 'perceived past,' doesn't that sound like wooden iron?" (Husserl 1966: 415; quoted by Brough 1989: 273). Husserl's way of dealing with this problem appears to come down to sticking to his guns, and denying the assumption that perception must always be of something that exists at the time of the perceiving itself. Retention is, allegedly, the direct intending of what is past.
[15] Retention, then, is the current, direct and "perceptual" intending, within finite limits, of past stages of the temporal object as past to some degree. Husserl is, effectively, describing an aspect of consciousness which is, theoretically, entirely novel. It is difficult to grasp clearly the nature of retention because it is essentially unlike any mental act as delineated by more familiar taxonomies (e.g., our everyday or "folk" sense of the kinds of mental acts that there are).

[16] Protention is basically the symmetrical opposite of retention, directed towards the future rather than the past. The major difference, of course, is that whereas the past has happened, and in that sense is fixed, the future is still open; there is certainly no way in which one can know what it will be. How then, one might ask, can protention - intendings of the future, modeled on perception - possibly exist? This really is very mysterious. Husserl had relatively little to say about it, except to suggest, in a quite unsatisfactory manner, that protention is somehow both determinate and open at the same time.

Cognitive Science and Time Consciousness

[17]  How does cognitive science deal with time consciousness? In fact, cognitive scientists have so far paid little, if any, attention to time consciousness as such. The topic is really a phenomenological one, in the sense that it was developed in the phenomenological tradition, and cognitive scientists have not come to treat it as a topic deserving attention in its own right. However, cognitive scientists have studied various aspects of cognition which are closely related to time consciousness, such as auditory pattern recognition, a special case of which is recognition of music. An essential feature of auditory patterns is that they happen in time; the particular way they unfold in time is what makes them the pattern that they are. Moreover, our perception of auditory patterns, such as melodies, is a classic case of time consciousness. If we can understand the mechanisms that enable us to recognize auditory patterns, we might obtain insight into how it is that, more generally, we can be aware of temporal objects as temporal.

[18] Cognitive scientists try to understand the causal mechanisms responsible for a given phenomenon by producing and analyzing models. There are at least two fundamentally different kinds of models, corresponding to what is arguably the deepest division between kinds of research in cognitive science. That is the division between the computational approach, on the one hand, and the dynamical approach on the other. Computationalism has dominated cognitive science since the discipline emerged in the fifties and sixties, and is still the mainstream or orthodox approach (see Pylyshyn 1984). It takes cognitive systems to be computers, in the quite strict and literal sense of machines which manipulate internal symbols in a way that is specified, at some level, by algorithms. Computers in this sense are exemplified by Turing Machines. Cognition, according to this approach, is the internal transformation of structures of symbolic representations. A classic example of mainstream computational modelling is the SOAR framework developed by Newell and others, within which detailed models of a wide variety of aspects of cognition have been developed (Newell 1991). Since cognition is taken to be the behavior of a computer, computer science provides the general conceptual framework within which cognition can be studied. Standing behind this approach to cognition is a long philosophical tradition, stretching from Plato through Descartes, Leibniz and Kant, and culminating in contemporary philosophers such as Fodor, which assumes that the essence of mind is to represent and reason about the world.

[19] What do computational models of auditory pattern recognition look like? At the most generic level, they work by applying recognition algorithms to symbolic encodings of the auditory information. This implies a two-stage process; one in which the auditory signal is encoded, and another in which the encoded information is analysed. As a consequence, there is a structural feature which all computational models share: the buffer. This is a kind of temporary warehouse in which the auditory information is stored in symbolic form as it comes in, in preparation for the recognition algorithms to do their work. This is achieved by sampling the auditory signal at a regular rate, i.e., using an independent clock to pick out points of time and measuring the signal at those times, then storing in the buffer symbolic representations of those measurements together with the time they were taken.

[20] The dynamical approach to cognitive science takes cognitive systems to be dynamical systems rather than computers.(2) In this context, a dynamical system is a set of quantities evolving interdependently over time. The solar system is the best-known example of a dynamical system; it consists of the positions and momentums of the sun and planets, all of which are changing all the time, in such a way that the current state of every quantity affects the way every other one changes. In cognitive science, most (though by no means all) dynamical models of cognition are neural networks, in which the set of interdependently evolving quantities are the activity levels of the neural units. According to the dynamical approach, cognition is not manipulation of symbols but rather state-space evolution within a dynamical system, and the emergence of order and structure within such evolution. The relevant conceptual framework is that of dynamics (dynamical modeling and dynamical systems theory), which may well be the most widely used and successful explanatory framework in the whole of natural science. Standing behind the dynamical approach is an alternative philosophical tradition, from Heidegger and Ryle earlier this century to contemporary figures such as Dreyfus and Varela, which takes the essence of mind to be ongoing active engagement with the world.

[21] What do dynamical models of auditory pattern recognition look like? At the most generic level, they work by having the auditory pattern influence the direction of evolution within the dynamical system. It will be useful to describe one such dynamical model in just a little detail. This is the Lexin model for auditory pattern recognition developed by Sven Anderson and Robert Port (Port, McAuley, and Anderson 1996). It is a neural network in which each of the system variables (neural units) changes its activity level as a function of the current activity of the other variables and the connections between them in a way that is determined by differential equations. For the general architecture of the network and the form of the governing differential equations see figure 2.

Figure 2: The Lexin dynamical model of auditory pattern recognition developed by Robert Port and Sven Anderson. On the right is a schematic depiction of the neural network architecture. On the left is the general form of the differential equations which govern the evolution of individual variables and hence change in the system as a whole.

[22] There are many subtleties about the particular organization and behavior of this network, but for current purposes we only need to understand the principles of its operation at the most generic level. The total state of the network at a given time is the set of values, at that time, of each of the neural units. This total state corresponds to a point in a geometric space of all possible total states. Every neural unit is continuously changing its activity under influence from other units, and so the total state of the system is itself continuously changing, or moving on a particular trajectory through the space. This trajectory can be diagrammed, in a very schematic way, by a curve on a plane. The shape of this curve can be affected by external factors. In other words, inputs to the system influence the direction of change in the system. If these inputs correspond to particular segments of the auditory pattern, then the curve will reflect not only the intrinsic tendencies of the system, but also the distinctive structure of the auditory pattern. In the Lexin model, particular sounds turn the system in the direction of unique locations in the state space, and if the system is exposed to nothing but a given sound, it will eventually end up just sitting at that point. When exposed to a sequence of distinct sounds, however, the system will head first to one location, then head off to another, waving and bending in a way that is shaped by the sound pattern, much as a flag is shaped by gusts of wind. In more technical terms, particular input frequencies constitute parameter settings which fix the location of unique point attractors; when the frequency changes, the system bifurcates, and the trajectory is fixed by this sequence of bifurcations ("attractor chaining").

[23] Now, how can an arrangement of this kind be understood as recognizing patterns? Recognizing a class of patterns requires discriminating those patterns from others not in the class, and this must somehow be manifested in the behavior of the system. One way this can be done is by having the system arrive in a certain state when a familiar pattern is presented, and not otherwise. That is, there is a "recognition region" in the state space which the system passes through if and only if the pattern is one that it recognizes. Put another way, there is a region of the state space that the system can only reach if a familiar auditory pattern (sounds and timing) has influenced its behavior. Familiar patterns are thus like keys which combine with the system lock to open the door of recognition.

Figure 3: A schematic depiction of the state space of the Lexin model, and a behavioral trajectory. Each point along the curved line represents a state of the system at a time. The shape of the curve is determined by a combination of the system's intrinsic behavioral tendencies and external influences. In this case, the system passes through the recognition region and thereby recognizes the external influences as constituting a familiar pattern. A successul auditory pattern recognition system of this type is one that will pass through the recognition region if, and only if, a familiar pattern is presented.

[24] The remarkable fact is that dynamical systems can in fact be configured so as to exhibit exactly this kind of response. This is what the Lexin model does with a small repertoire of relatively simple patterns. If this model is along the right lines, this is what our own auditory systems do with the vast repertoire of complex and subtle patterns that we can discriminate from the sea of noise around us.

Phenomenology Informs Cognitive Science

[25] We thus have two general approaches to the study of cognition, which have issued in two very different kinds of model of auditory pattern recognition. Which of these kinds of models is to be preferred? Their value is ultimately a matter of how they match up against all the relevant empirical data. It is difficult at the moment (and especially difficult for someone standing outside this particular discipline) to deliver any definitive judgement here. However, it is possible to make a more limited point of comparison, one which is directly relevant to the major aims of this paper. In this section I will suggest that phenomenological evidence weighs in on the side of dynamical models as opposed to computational models (at least as those two classes are sketched above).

[26] An obvious and superficially plausible objection to the computational approach in general has always been cognition does not seem to be a matter of manipulation of symbols inside the head. When one introspects on one's own thought processes, one generally doesn't observe the symbols and transformations that are alleged to constitute those processes. The standard way in which mainstream computational cognitive science has dealt with this objection is to suggest that the posited computational processes are subconscious, and so the phenomenology does not directly bear on the issue. This strategy is not simply a matter of self-serving selection of the kinds of evidence to be taken into account. There is no reason to assume that the phenomenology of a mental process should somehow give direct insight into the nature of the causal processes that subserve that phenomenology. By analogy, the picture on television gives no insight into the causal mechanisms that give rise to that picture (except, perhaps, in the very special case in which the program on television happens to concern how televisions work). In a certain sense, we "see through" the screen to the content that is conveyed by the television. In a similar way, we "see through" the mechanisms responsible for our cognitive processes.

[27]  Unfortunately, computationalists have, by and large, gone on illegitimately to assume a general license to ignore phenomenological data of any kind whenever it is convenient to do so. Their models are generally evaluated only by whether they match the measured performance data, and not by whether they make any sense in terms of our own observations of our experience. In the long run, however, this attitude cannot be sustained. Phenomenological evidence - both the everyday kind and the theoretically sophisticated deliverances of Husserl and others - is one source of relevant constraint among others. Like any other data, phenomenological evidence must be treated with care, but no theory of mind and cognition would be complete unless it could properly integrate causal mechanisms with phenomenology. Although phenomenological observation cannot, in general, be presumed to give direct insight into the nature of the mechanisms responsible for experiential phenomena, there must ultimately be an account of why those phenomena are the way they are given (at least partly) in terms of the nature of those mechanisms. For this reason, the nature of our experience should be regarded as having the potential to constrain our theories and models in cognitive science.

[28] Now, the phenomenological observation that is relevant here is simply a relatively obvious point on which Husserl relied when criticizing the Meinongian theory of time consciousness. Recall that, according to that theory, time consciousness is made possible by the presence of an additional mental act which surveys all the momentary stages and synthesizes them into a single apprehension of the object as a temporal whole. This act can only take place once all the momentary stages have occurred. However, attending to the nature of the experience involved, it seems clear that we do not have to wait until the temporal object is over before we can perceive it as a temporal object. I don't have to wait until the end of "Smells Like Teen Spirit" before experiencing it as the song that it is; indeed, I don't have to wait until the end of even a single bar. After perhaps an initial delay, every sound, on a moment by moment basis, is perceived as part of that tune. In short, time consciousness unfolds in the very same time frame as the temporal object itself.

[29] How does this observation bear on the difference between dynamical and computational models? Well, notice that computational models have the same temporal structure as the Meinongian account of time consciousness. In computational models, the auditory pattern is first encoded symbolically and stored in a buffer. Only when the entire pattern has been stored in the buffer do the recognition algorithms go to work; and it is only when those algorithms have done their work that the system could be said to have any kind of awareness of the pattern as such. It follows, therefore, that computational models are open to the very same objection as the Meinongian account. The fact is, in order to recognize a tune as such, we don't (as computational models suggest) have to wait until the end of the tune. I hear the tune as a tune even as the tune is playing.

[30] On the other hand, dynamical models exhibit exactly the kind of simultaneous unfolding that phenomenological observation suggests. The state of the system is always changing, and from the onset of the very first sound, the system is evolving in a direction which reflects both the auditory pattern itself and the system's familiarity with that pattern. In other words, the system begins responding to the pattern as the pattern that it is from the moment it begins.

[31] Clearly, then, dynamical models fit much better with the nature of our experience than do computational models. Other things being equal, this gives us good reason to prefer dynamical models over computational models; and if we accept this, then we have accepted that phenomenology can substantially constrain cognitive science.

[32] How might computationalists respond? One possibility is to deny or reinterpret the phenomenological evidence. Perhaps it merely seems that our experience of a tune unfolds while the tune is playing. Perhaps in fact all we have, while the tune plays, is a momentary awareness of the sound playing at each instant, and only when the tune is over do we comprehend the tune as a temporal whole. Perhaps, in Dennett's terms, the mechanisms of time consciousness do an Orwellian rewrite of the temporal history of our experience.

[33] Perhaps. Note, however, that there is no particular reason to believe this other than a desire to save computational models in an ad hoc way. We should presumably prefer a kind of explanation which does not require us to suppose that we are systematically deceived by our experience over one that does require this. Note also that the standard strategy employed by computationalists to discount phenomenological evidence, however plausible it might be in other cases, is not persuasive in this particular case. The actual time-course of my experience - how it happens in time - is not so obviously something that is conscious or subconscious in the normal sense. In any case, presumably the phenomenological conclusion can be tested by psychological ("third person") experiments which shed light on the actual temporal frame of experience and can indicate whether our sense of awareness of a temporal object as it unfolds is an illusion or not.

[34] Another kind of response would be to deny that a Meinongian structure is essential to computational models. Certainly, it is possible to imagine some kind of parallel-processing computational architecture which begins pattern recognition from the very moment the auditory event commences. This would be a major structural departure from current computational models, and parallel processing is always much easier envisaged than actually achieved. Perhaps it is not, after all, essential to computational models that they be broadly Meinongian. However, what is essential is that there be two theoretically distinct stages, one in which the auditory pattern is symbolically represented, and one in which algorithms operate on that symbolic representation. It is no accident that this theoretical distinction is universally reflected in the actual temporal structure of computational models; to avoid a Meinonginan structure is to work against the computational grain. In the long run, if what you need in your system is simultaneous coevolution, you may as well go with one that has it as a standard feature rather than with one that can only get it as an expensive aftermarket accessory.

Cognitive Science Informs Phenomenology

[35]  We have just seen how phenomenology can be relevant to cognitive science, giving a basis for preferring one kind of account of the underlying causal mechanisms over another. What about the other direction? How can cognitive science inform phenomenology?

[36] The main claim of this section is the bold one that cognitive science can tell us what retention and protention actually are, and in that sense deepen our understanding of them and of time consciousness in general. The case is parallel to that of genes. The theory of hereditary effectively dictated that there must be some mechanism of transferral of information from one generation to another, and specified the general properties that it must have. It was then up to the molecular biologists to discover what genes actually were, i.e., the chemical compounds and processes which in fact have the general properties. Likewise, Husserl's phenomenological theory specifies that time consciousness requires retention and protention, and the general properties they must have, and cognitive science uncovers the actual mechanisms which underlie time consciousness and instantiate retention and protention. In discovering what retention and protention actually are, we deepen our understanding of the phenomenological theory and may even be able to alter and improve that theory.

[37] When we understand how dynamical models of auditory pattern recognition work, we are already (without realizing it) understanding what retention and protention are. When we look at schematic diagrams of the behavior of these models, we are (without realizing it) already looking at schematic depictions of retention and protention. The key insight is the realization that the state of the system at any given time models awareness of the auditory pattern at that moment, and that state builds the past and the future into the present, just as Husserl saw was required.

[38] How is the past built in? By virtue of the fact that the current position of the system is the culmination of a trajectory which is determined by the particular auditory pattern (type) as it was presented up to that point. In other words, retention is a geometric property of dynamical systems: the particular location the system occupies in the space of possible states when in the process of recognizing the temporal object. It is that location, in its difference with other locations, which "stores" in the system the exact way in which the auditory pattern unfolded in the past. It is how the system "remembers" where it came from.

[39] How is the future built in? Well, note that a dynamical system, by its very nature, continues on a behavioral trajectory from any point. This is true even when there is no longer any external influence. The particular path it follows is determined by its current state in conjunction with its intrinsic behavioral tendencies. Thus, there is a real sense in which the system automatically builds in a future for every state that it happens to occupy. Now, if the current state is one that results from exposure to a particular auditory pattern, the future behavior of the system will itself be sensitive to that exposure. In other words, the system will automatically proceed on a path which (in practice) uniquely reflects the particular auditory pattern that it has heard up to that point. Thus, protention is also a geometric property of dynamical systems - indeed, the very same property as retention. Protention is the location of the current state of the system in the space of possible states, though this time what is relevant about the current state is the way in which, given the system's intrinsic behavioral tendencies, it shapes the future of the system. It is the current location of the state of the system which stores the system's "sense" of where it is going.

[40] The best way to tell whether these identifications are really appropriate is to compare retention and protention on the dynamical interpretation with the list of properties that Husserl ascribed to retention and protention. And in fact, they turn out to fit like hand and glove. Almost every description Husserl gave of retention and protention finds a natural interpretation in terms of the current location of a dynamical system capable of auditory pattern recognition such as the Lexin model. Considering retention first again:

  1. Current.
    The dynamical interpretation of retention identifies it with an aspect of the current state of the system, rather than any past or future aspect of the system.
  2. Intending of a stage as past to some degree.
    In these kinds of dynamical auditory pattern recognition systems, the location of the current state of the system reflects not just what previous sounds it had been exposed to, but also the order in which it was exposed to those sounds - or, more generally, how long ago it was exposed to that sound. Therefore, there is a clear sense in which retention, on this interpretation, intends the past as past to some degree.
  3. "Modification" of primal impressions.
    A primal impression is that "moment" of time consciousness which intends the current stage of the temporal object. In the case of tune recognition, it is the aspect of one's awareness of the tune as a whole which is awareness of the current note. On the dynamical account, awareness of the tune as a whole is identified with the current state of the auditory recognition system. The nature of these dynamical systems is such that current inputs act as parameters which influence how the system changes its state. More crudely, they push the system in one direction or another. The primal impression should therefore be identified with the way the system is currently changing under the influence of the current sound input. This gives us a clear interpretation of the claim that retention is modification of primal impression, for the locations of subsequent states of the system result directly from the way it is changing at any given time. Current change transmutes into future location.
  4. Continuous manifold.
    Dynamical auditory pattern recognition systems such as the Lexin model are continuous, both in the sense that the space of possible states is continuous and that their state changes continuously in that space in response to inputs which affect it continuously in time. Since retention is identified with system's occupying its current location in state space, and this location reflects past inputs, it makes sense to say that retention builds in the past in a continuous way. However, on this interpretation of what retention is, we find the very same awkwardness in using the term "retention" as a singular term as we found in the phenomenological account. There are no separate "retentions" distinct from each other and from the primal impression. The very idea of a manifold is an attempt to move from a set of things to an unbroken continuum, but we can now see that this term is unnecessary. Rather, there is a continuous retentional aspect to the current state of the system.
  5. Finite.
    It is a fact about these dynamical models that influence is "washed out" in the long run. Generally, the longer the state of the system is buffetted about by current inputs, the less the influence of a past input is discernible in the current state. There are not strict limits here, but it is clear that the current state does not retain the influence of inputs arbitrarily far in the past; thus, the current interpretation confirms the phenomenological insight that retention is finite.
  6. Direct: not memories, images, or echoes.
    Clearly, retention as explicated here does not relate to past stages of the temporal object via some other current mental act, such as a memory or an image or an echo. There is no space for any such additional acts in the model. In that sense, retention is direct.
  7. Perceptual.
    A strength of the dynamical interpretation of retention is that it does not underwrite exactly that aspect of retention that Husserl found most difficult to deal with and concerning which he was the least persuasive. In other words, if retention is the current location of the system, considered insofar as that current location reflects the past inputs, there is no clear way to make sense of retention as somehow perceptual in any substantial sense, and especially not perceptual with regard to something that no longer exists. The verdict must surely be that Husserl was mistaken in attempting to describe retention on a perceptual model. His own sense that to talk of perceptions of the past was tantamount to talk of "wooden iron" was entirely accurate; it is confused and unnecessary. From the perspective afforded by the dynamical interpretation, we can see both why Husserl felt compelled to talk that way - he had no better model of how something could "directly intend" the past - and yet encountered such difficulty in explaining just what this mysterious form of perception is.
[41] What about protention? Recall that on this account, protention is identified with the system's occupying its current location, since it is that location (in combination with the system's intrinsic dynamics, and keeping external influences fixed) which determines the future behavior of the system. This account makes sense of protention as current, intending future stages as future to some degree, as a continuous "manifold," as finite, and direct. Again, however, it demurs on Husserl's interpretation of protention as perceptual in character. Again, this is surely a strength of the account, since it removes precisely that aspect of protentions which were most mysterious. That is, when we interpret Husserlian phenomenology in the light of dynamical models of cognitive processes, we can see what is going on in such a way that we can make sense of protention as intending a possible future, but without doing so on a perceptual model, and hence removes any need to wonder how a protention can intend what might never even take place.

[42] Do these dynamical interpretations reveal what retention and protention actually are, or do they really show there is (after all) no such thing? This is a judgement call; it depends on the extent to which the dynamical models instantiate the properties which Husserl ascribed to retention and protention. My own opinion is that there is such a strong match that the right answer is that cognitive science is giving an alternative account of the very same theoretical postulates. However, this judgement requires rejecting one significant aspect of Husserl's interpretation of time consciousness, namely his idea that time consciousness requires, in some sense, the direct perception of the past and future. Rather, we can now understand better what retention and protention actually are, and can see how they can intend the past and future without perceiving them. Since this was the most problematic aspect of Husserl's account, this demonstrates how cognitive science can not only flesh out phenomenology, but actually improve it.

Conclusion

[43] Return to the paradox of time consciousness. That paradox was: how can I ever be aware of a temporal object as temporal, if I can only ever be aware of the current stage? Husserl grappled with this problem and developed a sophisticated phenomenological theory. Unfortunately, Husserl did not succeed fully in removing the sense of mystery concerning how time consciousness is possible; in particular, he believed he needed to invoke aspects of current awareness which somehow reach out perceptually to the past and the future. In some respects, Husserl's phenomenology of time consciousness can act as a powerful constraint on cognitive science itself, by (for example) providing a basis for preferring one whole class of models of the cognitive processes underlying auditory pattern recognition over another. Conversely, dynamical models provide a way of interpreting Husserl's phenomenology of time consciousness, and reveal what retention and protention really are. It is only when Husserl's theory is fleshed out and amended in the light of these dynamical models that the paradox of time consciousness is adequately dispelled.
This paper was prepared for the conference "Actualite De La Phenomenologie Husserliene: Les Defis De La Naturalisation," held in Bordeaux, France 19-21 October 19-21 1995, and will appear with revisions in the proceedings volume for that conference.

References

 
[1]
Blattner, W. (ms.). "Kant and Husserl on temporal synthesis and the consciousness of time."

 

[2]
Brough, J. (1989). "Husserl's phenomenology of time-consciousness." In J. N. Mohanty and W. R. McKenna (eds.), Husserl's Phenomenology: A Textbook, pgs. 249-290. Lanham MD: University Press of America.

 

[3]
Husserl, E. (1964). The Phenomenology of Internal Time- Consciousness. Martin Heidegger (ed.) and James S. Churchill (translator). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

 

[4]
--- (1966). Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußteins (1893/1917). Rudolf Boehm (ed.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

 

[5]
Miller, I. (1984). Husserl, Perception and Temporal Awareness. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

 

[6]
Newell, A. (1991). Unified Theories of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

 

[7]
Port, R. and T. van Gelder (1995). Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

 

[8]
Port, R., J. D. McAuley, and S. E. Anderson (1996). "Toward simulated audition in an open environment." In E. Covey, H. Hawkins, T. McMullen, and R. Port (eds.), Neural Representation of Temporal Patterns. New York: Plenum Publishing.

 

[9]
Pylyshyn, Z.W. (1984). Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science. Cambridge MA: Bradford/MIT Press.

Footnotes

 
(1)
Brough's treatment is especially useful for the non-specialist - comprehensive yet succinct, and very accessible. The current presentation is heavily based on Brough's work, though of course he must not be held accountable for its deficiencies.

 

(2)
For an overview of the dynamical approach, see (Port and van Gelder 1995).
 ©1996 Tim van Gelder
 EJAP is a non-profit entity produced at Indiana University. EJAP may not be printed, forwarded, or otherwise distributed for any reasons other than personal use. Do not post EJAP on public bulletin boards of any kind; use pointers and links instead. EJAP retains the right to continuously print all the articles it accepts, but all other rights return to the author upon publication. EJAP, Philosophy Department, Sycamore Hall 026, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN 47405.
The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 4 (Spring 1996)